Review for Pure Theory of law


Consider, for example, my first subject in pure sociology: law. The psychology of law addresses the individualistic aspect of the subject, including legal attitudes, perceptions, beliefs, and meanings, their origin, and their impact on legal decision-making. But the pure sociology of law entirely ignores the psychology of law. It reconceptualizes law as a social rather than a personal phenomenon. The subject becomes the behavior of law itself What does law do, and why? How does it vary with its location and direction in social space? The pure sociology of law not only differs from the psychology of law, but completely reverses the prevailing conception of legal action. No longer conceived as the action of a person (such as a citizen, police officer, or judge), it now becomes the action of law itself. A call to the police, for example, becomes law's movement into a particular conflict. The same applies to every instance of governmental social control, whether an arrest, prosecution, conviction, punishment, civil lawsuit, or civil remedy. Every such action is an increase of law in a particular case. And all increases of law are predictable and explainable with a single theory applicable across the social universe.
Law of every kind varies with its location and direction in social space, the social structure of each case-its geometry. Social space includes vertical, horizontal, cultural, corporate, and normative dimensions, and the multidimensional structure of every conflict predicts and explains the behavior of law in each (see Black 1976). From the standpoint of pure sociology, then, people do not use more or less law to pursue justice or other goals. Instead, conflict structures attract more or less law. There are litigious structures rather than litigious people, punitive and severe structures rather than punitive and severe people. People are irrelevant.
The behavior of law depends, for example, on the relational structure of each case: Law is a curvilinear function of relational distance (Black 1976: 40-46). This principle predicts that a conflict of any kind between strangers in any society will attract more law than the same conflict between family members or anyone else closer than strangers-and also more than a conflict between members of different societies. In modem America, for instance, it predicts that capital punishment will be more likely in homicide cases between strangers than in those between intimates. It similarly predicts calls to the police, arrests, lawsuits, who wins in court, and every other kind of variation in the amount of law-- with no reference whatsoever to the psychology of anyone involved. The principle of relational distance is not qualified by place or time but predicts and explains legal variation across societies and history, including the absence of law in bands of hunter-gatherers where everyone is intimate with everyone else and between tribes or nations with no relationship at all. Yet it meets all the highest standards of science-- testability, generality, simplicity, and so onand enjoys enormous empirical support, including numerous findings by anthropologists and historians (for a review of evidence, see, e.g., Black 1995: 842-44). No psychological theory of law (or anything else) predicts and explains as many facts so economically, precisely, and in a manner so easily testable across societies and history. Note, too, that the principle of relational distance has no ideological element (since it does not evaluate law or anything else), no teleological element (since it does not explain law as a means to an end), and no individualistic element (since it predicts the behavior of law instead of the behavior of people). It is a sociological law of law-a law of social life-something almost unimaginable before pure sociology.
I have applied the same paradigm to other subjects, such as the behavior of other social control, the behavior of ideas, the behavior of medicine, the behavior of science, and the behavior of God. There are violent structures and gossipy structures rather than violent and gossipy people, for instance, and there are scientific structures and religious structures rather than scientific and religious people (see, e.g., Black 1979; 1995; 1998: xviii-xxi; 2000a). Consider song and dance: Solo singing with precise pronunciation is a direct function of centralized authority, for example, and the number of body parts moved by dancers is a direct function of social stratification (see Lomax 1968: 121-40, 243-47). In this sense, the structure sings-not a person as such. The structure dances. The structure does everything. The person is sociologically dead (Black 1995: 870).
Pure sociology applies to all human behavior, including the behavior of people toward themselves-social life within the social structure of the self (see, e.g., Black 1992; 1995: 835). It also applies to the social life of nonhumans, and I have already extended it to the behavior of chimpanzees (Black 2000b: 114-16). Others have applied it to a wide variety of subjects as well (for references, see, e.g., Black 1995: 844-45, n. 88). And do not think that because pure sociology is so scientific and theoretical it has no practical value. On the contrary: It provides radically new directions for those who would change the world-a new source of what James Coleman calls "knowledgeable intervention" (1990: 4). The pure theory of law, for example, readily applies to practical matters such as winning legal cases, weakening the impact of social factors in the handling of legal cases, and reducing law itself (Black 1989: Chapters 2-5). Below I even address some practical implications of my pure theory of science. But first consider the behavior of sociology

Rewrite from Contemporary Sociology http://search.proquest.com/assets/r10.0.1-0/core/spacer.gif29. 5http://search.proquest.com/assets/r10.0.1-0/core/spacer.gif (Sep 2000): 704-709.

0 komentar:

Posting Komentar

 
Copyright © 2011 Arti, Pengertian, Definisi | Themes by ada-blog.com.